Imágenes de páginas
PDF
EPUB

No person is ignorant of primary and secondary qualities, a distinction much insisted on by philosophers. Primary qualities, such as figure, cohesion, weight, are permanent qualities, that exist in a subject whether perceived or not. Secondary qualities, such as colour, taste, smell, depend on the percipient as much as on the subject, being nothing when not perceived. Beauty and ugliness are qualities of the latter fort: they have no existence but, when perceived ; and, like all other secondary qualities, they are perceived intuitively; having no dependence on reason nor on judgement, more than colour has, or smell, or tafte (a). Quando

The qualities of right and wrong in yoluntary actions, are secondary, like beauty and ugliness and the other secondary qualities mentioned. Like them, they are objects of intuitive perception, and depend not in any degree on reason.

reason. No ment is requisite to prove, that to rescue an innocent babe from the jaws of a wolf, to feed the hạngry, to clothe the naked, are right actions : they are perceived to be fo intuitively. As little is an argument (4) Elements of Criticisin, vol. 1. p. 207, edit.'5.

requisite

No argu

requisite to prove, that murder, deceit, perjury, are wrong actions : they are perceived to be so intuitively. The Deity has bestow'd on man, different faculties for different purposes. Truth and falsehood are investigated by the reasoning faculty. Beauty and ugliness are objects of a sense, known by the name of taste. Right and wrong are objects of a sense termed the moral sense or conscience. And supposing these qualities to be hid from our perception, in vain would we try to discover them by any argument or process of reasoning: the attempt would be absurd; no less so than an attempt to discover by reasoning colour, or taste, or smell *

* Every perception must proceed from fome faculty or power of perception, termed sense. The moral sense, by which we perceive the qualities of right and wrong, may be considered either as a branch of the sense of seeing, by which we perceive the actions to which these qualities belong, or as a sense distinct from all others. The senses by which objects are perceived, are not separated from each other by distinct boundaries : the forting or clafling them, seems to depend more on taste and fancy, than on nature. I have followed the plan laid down by former writers; which is, to consider the moral sense as a sense distinct from others, because it is the eafieft and clearest manner of conceiving it.

Right

B 2

Right and wrong, as mentioned above, are qualities of voluntary actions, and of no other kind.t. An instinctive action may be agreeable, may be disagreeable ; but it cannot properly be denominated either right or wrong. An involuntary act is hurtful to the agent, and disagreeable to the spectator ; but it is neither right nor wrong. These qualities also depend in no degree on the event. Thus, if to save my friend from drowning I plunge into a river, the action is right, tho’ I happen to come too late. And if I aim a stroke at a man behind his back, the action is wrong, tho' I happen not to touch him.

The qualities of right and of agreeable, are inseparable; and so are the qualities

. of wrong and of disagreeable. A right action is agreeable, not only in the direct perception, but equally so in every

fubfequent recollection. And in both circumstances equally, a wrong action is disagreeable.

Right actions are distinguished by the moral sense into two kinds, what ought to be done, and what may be done, or left undone. Wrong actions admit not that distinction: they are all prohibited to be

done,

done. To say that an action ought to be done, means that we are tied or obliged to perform ; and to say that an action ought not to be done, means that we are restrained from doing it. Tho' the necesfity implied in the being tied or obliged, is not physical, but only what is commonlý termed moral; yet we conceive ourselves deprived of liberty or freedom, and necessarily bound to act or to forbear acting, in opposition to every other motive. The necessity here described is termed duty. The moral necessity we are under to forbear harming the innocent, is a proper example: the moral sense declares the restraint to be our duty, which no motive whatever will excuse us for transgressing.

The duty of performing or forbearing any action, implies a right in some person to exact performance of that duty; and accordingly, a duty or obligation necessarily infers a corresponding right. My promise to pay L. 100 to John, confers a right on him to demand performance. The man who commits an injury, violates the right of the person injured ; which entitles that person to demand reparation

of the wrong

Duty

Duty is twofold; duty to others, and duty to ourselves. With respect to the former, the doing what, we ought to do, is termed jufi : the doing what we ought not to do, and the omitting what we ought to do, are termed unjust. With refpect to ourselves, the doing what we ought to do, is termed proper : the doing what we ought not to do, and the omitting what we ought to do, are termed improper. Thus, right, fignifying a quality of certain actions, is a genus ; of which just and proper, are species : wrong, signifying a quality of other actions, is a genus ; of which unjust and improper are species.

Right actions left to our free will, to be done or left undone, come next in order. They are, like the former, right when done ; but they differ, in not being wrong when left undone. To remit a just debt for the sake of a growing family, to yield a subject in controversy rather than go to law with a neighbour, generously to return good for ill, are examples of this fpecies. They are universally approved as right actions: but as no person has a right or title to oblige us to perform such actions, the leaving them undone is not a

wrong:

[ocr errors][ocr errors]
« AnteriorContinuar »